•  

    Research 

     

    Klee, "Room with Northern Exposure" 1932

    Klee, "Room with Northern Exposure" 1932

    Published Articles

    The Probelm of Unarticulated Truths, Philosophical Studies 2023

    [published version] [preprint]

     

    In recent years, a variety of philosophers have argued that the fundamental bearers of representational properties like truth are concrete particulars produced by cognitive agents—representational vehicles (“RVs”), as I will call them. This view apparently conflicts with other judgments that are part of our common sense understanding of truth. For instance, it is plausible that there are truths about the Milky Way that have and never will never be articulated by anyone. Whatever these truths are, it looks like they cannot be RVs, because an RV is articulated just in case it exists. In this paper, I argue that it is consistent to hold that the fundamental truth-bearers are representational vehicles, while also acknowledging the existence of unarticulated truths. I argue that truth is a property that derivatively holds of kinds of RVs, that these provide the basis for our judgments that there are unarticulated truths, and I defend the view against putative counter-examples.

    Works in Progress

    Particularism about Truth and the Significance of Revenge 

     

    Many have suggested that all responses to the semantic paradoxes that aim to preserve classical logic face revenge paradoxes: they allow for the construction of further Liar-like objects regarding which they must either be silent or refute themselves. I consider this suggestion for the Particularist response to the paradoxes, the most sophisticated development of whichis found in Gaifman (1988, 1992, 2000). The hallmark of the Particularism is that it treats truth as a property of concrete particular representations, e.g. sentence tokens, and treats semantic pathology as arising from a token’s presence in a problematic dependency structure consisting of a network of tokens. Contra Bacon (2015, 2018) and others, I argue that Revenge arguments raise no significant challenge for the Particularist response. The Revenge sentence for the Particularist (roughly, u = “No token of u is true”) is only guaranteed to be pathological if it is understood as talking about tokens that are produced as elements of some specific interpreted language. I arguethat this should be understood in terms of a token’s being produced in a stable semantic state—a state of a linguistic agent that ensures the stable inheritance of meanings across tokens of the same linguistic type. The upshot of the Revenge Argument, I argue, is that no linguistic agent can articulate a complete truth theory for tokens produced in their own stable semantic state. This is an expressive limitation, but not an especially surprising one. I argue that the existence of this expressive limitation does not undermine the truth-theoretic virtues claimed for the Particularist response or Particularism’s claim to offer a fully general account of semantic pathology.

     

    Open Texture and Capacious Pluralism about Content

     

    The traditional view of propositional content presupposes that there is a privileged classification of token representations that partitions them with respect to sameness of content. I argue that there is no such thing: we utilize multiple distinct standards of sameness of content, none of which is privileged. My argument is based on the existence of semantic underdetermination. Plausibly, we use expressions (e.g. “sandwich”) that do not have determinate extensions and that are open to precisification in multiple directions. This gives rise to indefinitely many possible cases of content fission, where a semantically underdetermined token is identified as having the same content as two tokens that are precisified in opposite ways. Content fission requires recognizing a huge variety of legitimate notions of sameness of
    content.

     

    Thinking in Symbols and Leibniz's Theory of Demonstration

     

    From his earliest to his latest writings, Leibniz maintainedthat reasoning is calculation and that much of human thought is carried out in
    symbols. However, unlike “mental language” theorists like Ockham and Fodor,
    Leibniz does not think that human cognition is constituted as such bythe production and manipulation of mental symbols. Through his whole career, he
    contrasts thinking in symbols with thinking by means of ideas and claims that
    humans engage in both. I explicate Leibniz’s distinction between symbolic andideational thought as a distinction between thought that involves an
    intermediate sensible medium and thought that does not. In addition to marking
    an interesting psychological contrast, I argue that this distinction is of
    fundamental importance to Leibniz’s epistemology—specifically, his development
    of a non-Cartesian account of distinct cognition. According to Leibniz, distinct knowledge is manifested in an ability to give definitions and
    construct demonstrations. For Leibniz, both of these operations, I argue, must
    take place in symbolic rather than ideational thought. For Leibniz,symbolic thought is the mode in which the vast majority of cognitive
    achievement takes place for finite minds, because it is the medium in which we
    can develop the deductive systems that constitute distinct cognition.